Nature Institute logo

Evolution As It Was Meant To Be
A work in progress by
Stephen L. Talbott

Chapter 20

Evolution Writ Small

book home page / email alerts RSS Feed: RSS Feed for this page   
This is a preliminary draft of one chapter of a book-in-progress tentatively entitled, “Evolution As It Was Meant To Be — And the Living Narratives That Tell Its Story”. You will find here a fairly lengthy article serving as a kind of extended abstract of major parts of the book. This material is part of the Biology Worthy of Life Project. Copyright 2017-2019 The Nature Institute. All rights reserved. Original publication: May 7, 2019. Last revision: May 7, 2019.

Tags: development (ontogeny); evolution/and development

One might think that the natural place to look for an understanding adequate to the evolutionary history of life would be the powers of self-transformation we observe in the evolving organisms themselves. But it can be dangerous to look in a clear-eyed manner at the creative potentials of living beings. One risks having to acknowledge the evident wisdom and agency so vividly on display. In an era of institutionalized materialism, any suggestion that these inner powers are vital to the entire evolutionary story can only produce the sort of discomfort associated with a taboo and what I have been calling the biologist’s blindsight (Chapter 2).

On the other hand, Stephen Jay Gould ran afoul of no taboo when he effectively ascribed this same wisdom and agency to natural selection. Countering the questions we heard voiced in Chapter 19 about what sort of creative principle could explain the “arrival of the fittest”, he asked (referring to several giants of twentieth-century evolutionary biology), “Why was natural selection compared to a composer by Dobzhansky; to a poet by Simpson; to a sculptor by Mayr; and to, of all people, Mr. Shakespeare by Julian Huxley?”

The answer, Gould said, is that the allusions to poetry, musical composition, and sculpture helpfully underscore the “creativity of natural selection”:

The essence of Darwinism lies in its claim that natural selection creates the fit. Variation is ubiquitous and random in direction. It supplies the raw material only. Natural selection directs the course of evolutionary change. It preserves favorable variants and builds fitness gradually.1

On its face, Gould’s argument was a puzzling one. His answer to the question how creative variation arises amounted to saying nothing more than “It is everywhere” (“variation is ubiquitous”) — which, one might have thought, only added urgency to the need for an explanation. He seemed to suggest that, because organisms are so expert and prolific at producing new possibilities of life, the evolutionist can simply take their powers of achievement for granted. Because organisms so abundantly provide raw materials for creative work, we are somehow free to declare natural selection the agent performing this work. It need only preserve all those wonderfully effective new traits.

How easy it is, apparently, to forget that the so-called “raw materials” being preserved are never merely raw materials! At the first appearance of any beneficial change, the creative work has already been accomplished. We find ourselves looking, not at random raw materials, but at a viable feature harmoniously incorporated into all the tightly interwoven complexity of a living being. The only power we know to be capable of such incorporation is that of the organism telling its own story, a story always reflecting the qualitative, dynamic character and developmental potentials of a particular species.

This harmonious incorporation of new features, founded upon whole-cell inheritance and manifested in whole-organism processes of development, is the only place where we see creative evolutionary change originating. The spreading of an already-existing change through a population — almost the only thing those dominant evolutionary theorists known as “population geneticists” have attended to — is not where we see evolutionary novelties arising.

So Gould’s response shows us that one of the evolutionist’s strategies for coping with taboo agency is immediately to turn the question, “How does creative change arise?” into the different question, “How does creative change, once arisen, spread through a population?” The switch of topics is not hidden, but occurs in plain sight. Only a habit of blindsight relative to the organism’s agency seems able to explain the prevailing inattention to such an obvious evasion of a real biological question.

None of this means we need to doubt whatever is true in the idea of natural selection. As philosopher Ronald Brady summed it up, “simple selective pressure has never been seriously in question. That certain conditions can cause selective mortality means only that some alleles [genes] can be weeded out, not that this action can combine with variation in order to optimalize adaptation” (Brady 1979). Eliminating problematic traits (or defective organisms) is not the same thing as profoundly transforming the integral unity that every organism is.

The point is not terribly subtle. There is simply nothing in the idea of natural selection that points to the creative capacities necessary for producing new adaptive features — for producing, say, a four-chambered heart (with all its organism-wide implications) from a three-chambered one. There is only the living being whose agency and activity natural selection necessarily assumes and which, as a result of blindsight, evolutionists have unconsciously transferred to a mystical “mechanism” of selection somehow operated by the inanimate world.

So here is our main question for this chapter: What do organisms show us, directly, compellingly, and uncontroversially, about their own powers of organic transformation? Much of the first half of this book contributes to an answer, especially at the physiological and molecular levels of observation. But in the present, evolutionary context, it will be well to look at the organism from a new angle.

A ‘magical’ power of
self-transformation

If I were to tell you that scientists have sequenced the genomes of two entirely distinct organisms — say, a flying creature such as a bird or bat, and a crawling one such as an earthworm or snake — and had found the two genomes to be identical, you would probably think I was joking. Surely such differently structured forms and behaviors could not possibly result from the same genetic instructions! A genome, we’ve been told time and again, comprises a blueprint for, or otherwise corresponds to, a phenotype — that is, the manifest form and functions of an organism. And what could be more different than the phenotypes of snake and bird?

And yet a good reason for jettisoning the entire notion of “genetic instructions” is that there are flying and crawling creatures with the same genetic sequence. A monarch butterfly and its larva, for example. Nor is this kind of thing rare. A swimming, “water-breathing” tadpole and a leaping, air-breathing frog are creatures with the same inherited DNA. Then there is the starfish: its bilaterally symmetric larva swims freely by means of cilia, after which it settles onto the ocean floor and metamorphoses into the familiar form of the adult. This adult, carrying the genome passed on from its larval stage, exhibits an altogether different, radially symmetric (star-like) body plan.

Box 20.1

Metamorphosis of an Insect

goliath beetle larva (Goliathus goliatus) goliath beetle adult (Goliathus goliatus)

The goliath beetle (Goliathus goliatus), larva and adult.2

The British physician and evolutionary scientist, Frank Ryan, described the goliath beetle’s metamorphosis this way:

“Rather than a den of repose, we see now that the enclosed chamber of the goliath’s pupa really is a crucible tantamount to the mythic pyre of the phoenix, where the organic being is broken down into its primordial elements before being created anew. The immolation is not through flame but a voracious chemical digestion, yet the end result is much the same, with the emergence of the new being, equipped with complex wings, multifaceted compound eyes, and the many other changes necessary for its very different lifestyle and purpose.

“The emerging adult needs an elaborate musculature to drive the wings. These muscles must be created anew since they are unlike any seen in the larva, and they demand a new respiratory system — in effect new lungs — to oxygenate them, with new breathing tubes, or tracheae, to feed their massive oxygen needs. The same high energy needs are supplied by changes in the structure of the heart, with a new nervous supply to drive the adult circulation and a new blood to make that circulation work.

“We only have to consider the dramatic difference between a feeding grub or caterpillar and a flying butterfly or a beetle to grasp that the old mouth is rendered useless and must be replaced with new mouthparts, new salivary glands, new gut, new rectum. New legs must replace the creepy-crawly locomotion of the grub or caterpillar, and all must be clothed in a complex new skin, which in turn will manufacture the tough new external skeleton of the adult. Nowhere is the challenge of the new more demanding than in the nervous system — where a new brain is born. And no change is more practical to the new life-form than the newly constructed genitals essential for the most important new role of the adult form — the sexual reproduction of a new generation.

“The overwhelming destruction and reconstruction extends to the very cells that make up the individual tissues, where the larval tissues and organs are broken up and dissolved into an autodigested mush … To all intents and purposes, life has returned to the embryonic state with the constituent cells in an undifferentiated form” (Ryan 2011, pp. 104-5).

Millions of species consist of such improbably distinct creatures, organized in completely different ways at different stages of their lives, yet carrying around the same genetic inheritance. (See Box 20.1.) This is some­thing to reflect on. How could the trans­form­a­tion possibly be orchestrated, and where lies the power of orchestration?

To speak of the “power of orchestration” will perhaps trigger accusations of “mysticism”. And yet the expression of some power is right there before our eyes. It is hardly anti-science to let ourselves come up against questions we cannot yet answer. They are what science is for.

One way or another we must come to terms with the fact that the organism and its cells actively play off the genomic sequence and all the other available resources within a huge space of profoundly creative possibility. No identifiable physical force compels or directs the cell-by-cell and molecule-by-molecule dissolution and refashioning described in Box 20.1. It is only healthy that such difficulties for our understanding should be acknowledged.

Looking at the pupal case of a fly, the developmental biologist and evolutionary theorist, Wallace Arthur, asked: “What on earth is going on in there to turn one animal into another? If we didn’t know better, we might venture ‘magic’ as our best attempt at an answer” (Arthur 2004, p. 45). Arthur’s wonder is justified. And he surely expects, as we must, that a more satisfactory answer than “magic” will be forthcoming. Meanwhile, it is worth keeping in mind that the “magical” impression of a phenomenon becomes more powerful in direct proportion to the inadequacy of our existing explanatory resources.

Metamorphosis of cells

Frogs and butterflies aside, we are brought up against the same perplexities even when we consider the more “routine” developmental processes in complex organisms. Take, for example, the radical cellular transformations following from a single, fertilized human egg cell. As adults, we incarnate ourselves in trillions of cells, commonly said to exemplify at least 250 major types. And when we count subtypes and transient types, we may well find that — as cell biologists Marc Kirschner and John Gerhart tell us — there are “thousands or tens of thousands of kinds representing different stable expression states of the genome, called forth at different times and places in development” (Kirschner and Gerhart 2005, pp. 179-81).

As researchers hone their ability to investigate single cells, they are finding that even neighboring cells, “identical” in type and occupying the same tissue or niche, reveal great heterogeneity. Every cell is, in whatever degree, “doing its own thing”. The path from the zygote through the many intermediate stages of cell differentiation to a particular mature cell type is a path that, for every cell, takes a novel course. It is a distinct cellular “evolution”, or active unfolding of potential.

Strikingly, however, the cell is not only doing its own thing; it is also heeding the “voice” of the surrounding context, which is in turn an expression of the unity of a particular kind of organism. So each cell is disciplined by the needs of its immediate cellular neighborhood as well as those of the entire developing organism, which in turn is conditioned by the larger environment. We are looking at a remarkable diversity within an overall, integral unity.

In humans there are, for example, cells (neurons) that send out extensions of themselves up to a meter or more in length, while being efficient at passing electrical pulses through the body. There are contractile cells that give us our muscle power. There are the crystalline-transparent fiber cells of the lens of the eye; their special proteins must last a lifetime because the nucleus and many other cellular organelles (prerequisites for protein production) are discarded when the fibers reach maturity. There are cells that become hard as bone; as easily replaceable as skin; as permeable as the endothelial cells lining capillaries; and as delicately sensitive as the various hair cells extending into the fluids of the inner ear, where they play a role in our hearing, balance, and spatial orientation.

Many of these cells are as visibly and functionally different, in their own way, as the phenotypes of any two organisms known to us. This, you might think, would interest the evolutionary biologist.

Organisms manage their
own germlines expertly

Of all the cellular phenotypes, it would be hard to find one whose differentiation and specialization is more distinctive, or more expertly and intricately contrived, or more purposively managed, than the germ cells of sexually reproducing organisms. We can hardly help acknowledging that parental organisms, in carrying out meiosis, genetic recombination, and mating, play a massive role, not only in preserving and re-purposing the genome, but also in transforming it. Deeply embedded in time and always facing the future, every sexually reproducing animal expresses its future orientation most immediately and vividly in the gametes whose full “self-realization” belongs to the next generation.

A gamete is at least as specialized as any other cell of the body. At the same time, this gamete, along with the entire lineage leading up to it, must retain the potential to yield the totipotent zygote. That is, despite its commitment to a highly specialized, reproductive function unlike that of any other cell type in the body, the germline cell must at the same time preserve within itself the flexibility and freedom that will be required for producing every cellular lineage of a new organism.

It is an extraordinary mandate, and our bodies must focus extraordinary powers of development upon it. For example, the chromosomes of both sperm and egg will have been modified by epigenetic “marks” (Chapter 8), ensuring that certain genes in the offspring will be active, or repressed, depending on which parent the gene was inherited from. Other widespread marks imposed by the parents will (for the most part) be erased immediately after fertilization. This leaves space for the new organism to structure the spatial, electrical, and chemical characteristics of its chromosomes (and therefore also its gene expression) according to its own developmental potentials.

And, of course, there is the elaborately orchestrated “meiotic ballet” (Page and Hawley 2003) that produces both sperm and egg, each with only half the number of chromosomes found in somatic cells, and with those chromosomes reshuffled and otherwise modified according to a logic and via activities that are still largely beyond any comprehensive understanding.

But one thing is sure: the body’s rearrangement (“recombination”) of its chromosomes during meiosis is now showing itself to be highly regulated. Multiple protein complexes and epigenetic modifications of chromosomes function combinatorially, with synergism, antagonism, and redundancy: “The new-found multiplicity, functional redundancy and [evolutionary] conservation” of these regulatory factors “constitute a paradigm shift with broad implications” (Wahls and Davidson 2012).

So we are given no choice but to think of the germline as an expression of that same agency — that same, end-directed transformative power — through which our body subtly, elaborately, and adaptively directs each of its other cell lineages toward a distinctive form and functioning within the unity of the whole. We have seen that this power of transformation comes to expression in the entire cell, quite apart from any mutations in its DNA. And it is just a fact that an entire cell is what each parent passes on as an inheritance to its offspring.

It would be strange indeed if the organism’s ability to proceed adaptively and creatively along paths of developmental transformation were to become frozen at the very point where, via the most sophisticated activity imaginable, it prepares its whole-cell bequest for the next generation. Can we reasonably claim that this is the one cell lineage in which the organism’s normal, future-oriented activity goes silent? Or that, with all the organism’s expertise at producing, adapting, and stably maintaining diverse phenotypes even without changes in DNA sequence, it “refuses” to employ this expertise when it comes to the preparation of inheritances? Or that the power with which the organism conforms all its cells, tissues, and organs to a unified and integral whole adapted as far as possible to current conditions is a power lost to it in the management of its own germline?

If every organism is a living agent, as we all know it to be (whether blindsightedly or otherwise), then surely that agency — whatever its nature, and however conditioned and constrained — is the decisive thing passing between generations. If every organism is an activity, a power of becoming, then the inheritance preparing the way for a new life must first of all be an inheritance of this active power, not of some fixed, already achieved, material result of it. And yet our science has not even addressed the problem of this formative power, let alone asked what role its unfolding expression — its development of its own potentials — might play in evolution.

A strangely absolute
demand for stable
variation

There could hardly be a more frequently stated requirement for natural selection than this: any beneficial genetic or other variation occurring in an organism, if it is to be evolutionarily relevant, must be stable, heritable, and long-lasting down through the generations. If a given variation is likely to pass away after a generation or two, or if it quickly suffers further change, then the normally long and slow process of selection will not have time to spread the variation (“fix it”) throughout a population.

We should note that here we have already left behind the question about the origin of new traits in favor of the question about their widespread establishment in a population. But the conventional answer to this second question, with its call for stable variation, is highly problematic — and revealing — in its own terms.

Richard Dawkins approaches the matter with his customary verve and ability to highlight the core defects of evolutionary theory as if they were its chief assets. In order for a genetic variation to be useful, he says, it must be “potentially eternally heritable”. “I’m not wedded to DNA”, he adds, but “I am wedded to this operational criterion that alterations in it go on forever potentially.”3

What he means is that useful variations are the ones selected for — maybe not eternally, but at least for a long time. The ones that are less than useful are selected against, and therefore are not eternal. But the truly beneficial adaptations can be selected and selected again, generation after generation, without any in-principle limitation. They are in this sense “potentially eternally heritable”, which can only be the case if they are extremely stable.

And yet, this stability criterion is wholly dependent upon the biologist’s unmindfulness of the organism’s agency. In contradiction to everything we know about organic activity, the assumption is made that variation results from processes altogether lacking the kind of coordination and adaptation to circumstances, the end-directedness and future-orientation, characteristic of all living activity we have ever observed. Variation, on this view, originates in more or less random rearrangements of “particles” (genes).

Once this sort of mindless rearrangement is substituted in our minds for living agency, there is, so the thinking goes, only one way a new trait, appearing first in just one or a few organisms, can become distributed throughout a large population: it requires a prolonged and more or less chancy play of life, competition, and death. Any transgenerational instability in the trait would make its fixation in the population via this process highly unlikely.

Unfortunately for the consistency of this point of view, the organism’s agency, while blindsightedly ignored as far as possible, is still assumed at every point of the theory. In their mere existence — let alone in their struggles for life, their mating, and their generation of inheritances — organisms display all the features of purposive, future-oriented beings. Only by means of these features can there be anything remotely like a “play of life, competition, and death”. But, at the same time, these features hardly support the idea that this play is merely “chancy”.

And, in fact, virtually every statement about the “mechanisms” of evolution in the literature today is rooted in the unspoken, unnoticed conviction that organisms routinely exercise the agency and purposive initiative central to their life. The conviction is so clearly underwritten by everyday perception that it need not even be mentioned. But when the failure to mention it turns into a “conspiracy of silence”, so that our theories of evolution must ignore the obvious, then something has gone badly wrong. (For one illustration of the problem here, see Box 20.2.)

Box 20.2

How Not to Explain Purposive Activity

All biologists find themselves saying that organisms, in their physiology and behavior, carry out functions. These functions broadly constitute the subject matter requiring biological explanation. References to them are one way of acknowledging the task- and future-oriented character of living activity, since to carry out a function is to coordinate means in the service of an end.

This end-directed activity seems to imply what we might call “interior being” — some form of intention and purposiveness in particular — and therefore demands that taboo-conscious biologists find a means to explain it away. The standard expedient is to say something like this: “Functions express the adaptedness of organisms, and adaptedness in general results from natural selection”. Every well-adapted trait exists because it (or a precursor) was once evolutionarily selected for its machine-like effectiveness as a function. This supposedly has nothing to do with any actual agency or intention on the part of organisms.

And yet, anyone who considers the core logic of natural selection, as discussed in Chapter 19, can hardly help noticing that the logic relies centrally upon organisms being capable of carrying out all the activities necessary to their life and “struggle for survival”. It also requires organisms capable of reproducing and preparing an inheritance for their offspring. In other words, it requires living beings with precisely those features that presented us with the problem of purposive activity in the first place.

But if natural selection, in order to operate, must take for granted all the familiar forms of living activity — and who does not see this? — then to say selection explains biological purposiveness looks very much like question-begging (Talbott 2017).

Putting it a little differently: purposiveness and agency are not particular functions, or traits, that arose at some point in organisms previously lacking the trait. They are, rather, features synonymous with life as far as we know it. They are necessarily assumed in any evolutionary process we can even conceive as such, and therefore cannot be explained as the result of an evolutionary process.

The problem has not been entirely missed. In 1962 the philosopher Grace de Laguna wrote a paper in which she remarked that only when we regard the organism as already “end-directed” does it “make sense to speak of ‘selection’ at all” (de Laguna 1962).

Moreover, a principle of stability looks rather odd as a fundamental principle of evolutionary change. When we trace a differentiating cell lineage in a developing organism, we watch one cell generation succeeding another, not by stably preserving change, but by compounding it — changing again what has just been changed. This is the change of a transformative, organic narrative, not a mere rearrangement of Newtonian particles being pushed about by external forces.

But think what this means. If many developmental changes are not stable and heritable over any large number of cellular generations, it is because they had better not be. After all, the cell lineage is on the way to somewhere, proceeding directionally along a pathway of integral, holistic transformation. This suggests how differently we may have to look at evolutionary processes when we are willing to acknowledge the nature of organic change and agency.

For example, the usual criticism of epigenetic factors as evolutionary causes — namely, that they often are not preserved endlessly down through subsequent generations — simply misses the whole character of organic change. It does so because the agency working through integral, living populations — whether those populations consist of the trillions of cells in our bodies or the myriad organisms in a community — has been blindsighted out of the picture.

I understand that some may view my rather casual transition in that previous sentence — the transition from cells in a body to organisms in a population — as a rather startling attempt to bridge an impassable gulf between development and evolution. To those concerned about this, I can only advise: read further.

Meanwhile, summing up the present chapter: the powerful adaptive plasticity whereby organisms undergo concerted developmental change looks like exactly the sort of change — the only sort of change we know about — that might translate, upon a wider stage, into the diverse organic transformations of evolution. The bare logic of natural selection, after all, makes no reference to the specific potentials concretely realized in the distinctive evolutionary trajectories leading from the simplest cells to redwoods and wildebeest, crayfish and cormorants. On the other hand, do we not discover something very like those potentials playing out in the distinctive developmental trajectories leading from a single-celled zygote to osteoblast and endothelium, neuron and neutrophil? And also when we watch the goliath beetle larva (or human embryo) metamorphosing into the adult form?

Only when we ignore the living powers required for such transformations can we subconsciously transfer our ineradicable sense of these powers to the working of a blind evolutionary algorithm (Chapter 19).

Once having learned to avoid such a mistake, we may reflect that, just as individual cells participate in the life of a complex organism, so, too individual organisms participate in the life of a population, or species. In neither case is it always easy to distinguish what is individual from what is collective. And this suggests that the agency we recognize in individual organisms cannot be cleanly separated from the agency at work in the species — surely an idea the evolutionary theorist might run with. I will now pick up this idea — not because it is a speculation worth exploring, but because its mundane truth is forced upon us by everything in front of our eyes, if only we will see it.

Notes

1. Gould 1976. By the time Gould completed his 2002 masterwork, The Structure of Evolutionary Theory, he would offer a richly nuanced qualification of these statements. But his fundamental belief in the creative role of natural selection — or, as he would say, its “efficacy” — remained.

2. Goliath beetle larva and adult photo credit: Frantisek Bacovsky.

3. Dawkins 2009. My quotations are transcribed from the conclusion of part 3 of a three-part recording of a debate, “Homage to Darwin”, held at Oxford University, May 8, 2009. Participants in the debate included Richard Dawkins, Lynn Margulis, Steve Bell, and Martin Brasier. The event was chaired by Oxford’s Denis Noble.

Tags: development (ontogeny); evolution/and development

Sources:

Arthur, Wallace (2004). Biased Embryos and Evolution. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.

Brady, Ronald H. (1979). “Natural Selection and the Criteria by Which a Theory Is Judged”, Systematic Biology vol. 28, pp. 600-21. Available online at the Nature Institute website

Dawkins, Richard (2009). Comments during “Homage to Darwin” debate, Balliol College, Oxford University (May 8). Audio of part 3 of the debate (from which my quotations are transcribed) is available at http://www.voicesfromoxford.org/homage-to-darwin-part-3-general-discussion/ (downloaded October 25, 2019). The quoted remarks by Dawkins begin at about 1:31:20 of the recording. Links to all three of the parts can be found at http://www.voicesfromoxford.­org/?s=homage+to+darwin

de Laguna, Grace A. (1962). “The Role of Teleonomy in Evolution”, Philosophy of Science vol. 29, no. 2 (April), pp. 117-31. doi:10.1086/287855

Gould, Stephen Jay (1976). “This View of Life: Darwin’s Untimely Burial”, Natural History vol. 85, pp. 24-30.

Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

Kirschner, Marc W. and John C. Gerhart (2005). The Plausibility of Life: Resolving Darwin’s Dilemma. New Haven CT: Yale University Press.

Page, Scott L. and R. Scott Hawley (2003). “Chromosome Choreography: The Meiotic Ballet,” Science vol. 301 (Aug. 8), pp. 785-9. doi:10.1126/science.1086605

Ryan, Frank (2011). The Mystery of Metamorphosis: A Scientific Detective Story. Foreword by Dorion Sagan and Lynn Margulis. White River Junction VT: Chelsea Green Publishing.

Talbott, Stephen L. (2017). “Evolution and the Purposes of Life”, The New Atlantis #51 (Winter). http://thenewatlantis.com/publications/evolution-and-the-purposes-of-life

Steve Talbott :: Evolution Writ Small